In this post, I wish to highlight what I take to be an important but under-appreciated disanalogy between rationally permissible belief and rationally permissible action. I will say more about why I think this disanalogy is under-appreciated in later posts. For now, I will simply attempt to identify the disanalogy, and say something about why it exists.
Consider
the following example of an agent engaged in a piece of practical deliberation:
Example 1: Lorry Driver Intention
A
lorry driver, Jesse, is trying to decide between continuing to drive down a
long stretch of road or stopping for a break.
After weighing all the considerations in favour of continuing to drive
(e.g., she is more likely to make her delivery on time) and all the
considerations in favour of taking a break (e.g., she would be able to get some
much deserved shut-eye), she comes to the conclusion that the total evidence
available is inconclusive either way.
She has just as much reason to continue driving as she does to stop and
take a break. Jesse decides to flip a coin: ‘head-side-up’ for continuing to drive,
and ‘tail-side-up’ for stopping for a break.
When the coin lands ‘tail-side-up’, Jesse pulls the lorry off to the side of
the road and removes the key from the ignition.
I take the
following three claims to be uncontroversially true about the agent is Example 1:
(1) The fact that Jesse decided to flip a coin and the coin landed tails-side-up explains why she decided to stop driving.
(2) The fact that Jesse decided to flip a coin and the coin landed tail-side-up does not justify her decision to stop driving.
(3) Jesse is not guilty of any irrationality for basing her decision to stop driving on the fact that she decided to flip a coin and the coin landed tail-side-up.
Now,
consider the following modified version of the Lorry Driver Intention example:
Example 2: Lorry Driver Belief
Jesse,
the lorry driver, is trying to determine if the following the proposition is true:
(H): “My lorry will run out of petrol before the next station”. However, suppose that all the evidence
available is inconclusive. Jesse has
just as much evidence in favour of (H) as she does against (H). She therefore decides to flip a coin. Assigning the value of ‘true’ to head-side-up, and
‘false’ to tail-side-up, and proceeds to flip a coin.
When the coin lands head-side-up, Jesse comes to believe (H). Jesse radios her dispatching and reports that
she believes her lorry will run out of petrol before the next station. When she is asked why she believes this, she
explains that since all the evidence she has available was inconclusive, the
decided to flip a coin. Incredulous, the
dispatcher points out that a coin flip fails to constitute evidence one way or
the other. Jesse agrees, but insists
that the coin flip remains the basis of her belief.
I take the
following three claims to be uncontroversially true about the agent in Example 2:
(1) The fact that Jesse decided to flip a coin and the coin landed heads-side-up explains why she believes the lorry will run out of petrol.
(2) The fact that Jesse decided to flip a coin and the coin landed heads-side-up does not justify her belief that the lorry will run out of petrol.
(3) Jesse is guilty of irrationality for basing her belief that she will run out of petrol on the fact that she decided to flip a coin and the coin landed heads-side-up.
In
contradistinction to the first example, the agent in the second example appears
to display gross irrationality. This
suggests an important disanalogy between rationally permissible belief and
rationally permissible action. While an agent’s actions may be rationally
permissible even though the explanation of her action fails to justify her
action, the same cannot be said of an agent’s beliefs.
I will now attempt to offer an explanation of why the above disanalogy between rationally permissible belief and action exists:
Theoretical
deliberation always involves a choice between three doxastic attitudes:
believing, disbelieving, or withholding belief and disbelief. This means failing to believe that P does not entail disbelieving P and failing to disbelieve P does not entail believing P.
Withholding P always remains an option. Withholding P, as I am using the expression, is not the same as failing to
adopt an attitude of belief and disbelief towards P. One may fail to adopt an
attitude of belief and disbelief towards P
because one has simply not considered P. In such a case, one neither believes nor
disbelieves P. But one is not withholding P either. One simply has not taken any attitude
towards P. In short, withholding P is as much an attitude towards P as believing or disbelieving P.
I
believe that the disanalogy between reasons for belief and reasons for actions,
highlighted in the previous section, is tied to the absence of a practical
analogue to withholding. Consider once again the lorry driver who has to decide
between continuing to drive and stopping for a break. The lorry driver’s decision has a zero-sum
structure. If she adopts the intention to continue driving, she has ipso facto adopted the intention not to
take a break. The same is true, mutatis
mutandis, if she adopts the intention to take a break. There is no attitude of
practical withholding that she may adopt as an end point of her deliberative
process. In sum, while there are three possible doxastic attitudes one can take
towards P—believing P, disbelieving P, and withholding P—there
are only two possible volitional attitudes one can take towards an
outcome—intending to bring about P and
intending not to bring about P. On the present analysis, not intending to
bring about P is not an attitude
towards bringing about P but rather
the absence of an attitude towards bringing about P.
In
cases in which the weighing of evidence is relevant, one must have net evidence
in favour of believing or disbelieving in order for either attitude to be
rationally permissible. Believing P is rationally permissible only if
one’s net evidence is in favour of P. Disbelieving P is rationally permissible only if one’s net evidence is against P.
If one lacks any evidence for or against P or if one has equal amounts of evidence both for and against P, then one is rationally obligated to
withhold P. Hence, since the agent
in the second example has equal amounts of evidence both for and
against the truth of the claim that her lorry will run out of petrol, she is rationally obligated to withhold belief. By contrast, she could have no analogous
obligation when it comes to the question of whether she should continue or stop
driving since withholding from both is simply not an option. Hence, even if she has equal amounts of
evidence in favour of continuing to drive and stopping for a break, she still has to do one or the other. Simply put, practical withholding is not an option. The upshot is that, unlike belief, there cannot be a requirement that an agent's net evidence favour a course of action in order for that course of action to be rationally permissible.
2 comments:
Hey Avery, some thoughts on this. The uses of the coin toss in the two cases don't seem quite analogous. In the first story Jesse flips the coin over whether or not she should take the action in question. In the second story Jesse flips the coin over whether the proposition is true or false. But the analogy seems rather to be whether or not she should believe the proposition or not. (Or, alternately, she should be flipping the coin in the first story over whether it would be best to pull over or not). For in the first the outcome of the coin toss directly decides the matter, whereas in the second the coin toss seems to require the further step "And Jesse resolves to believe the proposition if it is true, and disbelieve it if it is false" if it is to tie directly into the belief.
This matters because in your analysis the coin toss is appropriate in the action-case because the matter at hand affords a natural binary division (where opting to do one is de facto opting not to do the other), whereas this is not the case for belief. But if the coin toss was telling us "Believe or not believe" (where covered under "not believe" was both "Disbelieve" and "Withhold judgement") then both cases would afford this binary division. Yet I should still agree that the coin toss was a sensibel decision procedure in the first case but not the second. This suggests to me that your analysis of what the source of the dis-analogy is is off.
Hey Liam, thanks for the very thoughtful feedback! I am not convinced that my examples are disanalogous in the way you suggest. However, I suspect that I may need to phrase my examples more carefully in order to make the analogy between the two cases more transparent.
Notice that Jesse does not deliberate about whether or not to adopt a certain intention (i.e., the intention to take a break or the intention to continue driving). She deliberates about whether she should take a break or continue driving. This suggests that the appropriate theoretical analogue to her practical deliberation is not deliberating about whether to "believe or not believe" P. Rather, it is deliberating about whether or not P is true. Moreover, I don't think we typically deliberate about whether to "believe or not believe" something (though we might). We typically deliberate about whether or not something is true. Consider: if I were to deliberate about whether or not it would be best or most advantageous to believe P, my deliberation may be accurately described as deliberating about whether to "believe or not believe" P, but it can hardly be described as deliberating about whether or not P is true. Moreover, if I switch the focus of my second example to deliberating about whether to believe P, rather than to deliberation about whether P is true (as you seem to be suggesting), there seems to be a danger of collapsing the distinction between the theoretical and practical deliberation. After all, many practical considerations may go into determining whether or not I should believe that P. (I think William James would like that point.) However, we would then have something less like an analogy and more like an equivalence.
Another way of putting my point is as follows: The aim of theoretical deliberation (as I am conceiving it) is not the fixation of belief (Pierce be damned) but to bring my mental representations into conformity with the external world. Fixing belief is simply a matter of achieving a certain psychological state, and (in principle) this is something I can do without any concern for the extra-mental world. However, trying to bring my mental representations into conformity with the world betrays a fundamental concern with the extra-mental world. (I suspect that there are de re/de dicto issues in the vicinity, here, but I trust that my point is clear.) Analogously, the aim of practical reasoning (as I am conceiving it) is not the fixation of intention (i.e., achieving a certain psychological state), but to bring the extra-mental world into conformity with my mental representations. On this view, Jesse's coin toss (in both the theoretical and practical case) is meant to address an extra-mental concern.
Perhaps I could bring out this analogy more clearly if I rephrased my first example so that Jesse is deliberating about whether or not to make it true that P, where P is the proposition: "I am stopping for a break". This rephrasing would coincide with my preferred way of describing how conative attitudes like intentions relate to a proposition: to wit, while the belief that P represents P as true, the intention to bring about P represents P as to be made true. Does that make the analogy clearer? Or have I missed the force of your objection?
Post a Comment