In
his 2018 volume, The Importance of Being
Rational, Errol Lord defends the thesis that “what it is to be rational is
to correctly respond to possessed objective normative reasons” (p. 3). Lord calls this thesis “Reasons
Responsiveness”. According to Lord, Reasons
Responsiveness entails the following principle:
Equivalence:
Necessarily,
you are rational if and only if you correctly respond to reasons. (Lord 2018, p.
23)
In
this blog post, I will briefly explain why I believe that Equivalence—and by
extension, Reasons Responsiveness—is false.
To
better appreciate Lord’s proposal, let us consider how it explains the
irrationality incurred from having inconsistent beliefs or intentions. Many (if not most) contemporary action
theorists attempt to explain why it is irrational to have inconsistent beliefs
or intentions in terms of something along the lines of the following wide scope
norms.
Belief Consistency:
Rationality
requires that [if one believes P, then one does not believe ¬P]
Intention
Consistency:
Rationality
requires that [if one intends to F, then one does not intend to ¬F]
Lord
deems such wide scope norms unnecessary given that the same explanatory work
may be done by Reasons Responsiveness. Simply put, in all cases in which an
agent has inconsistent beliefs or intentions, they are also failing to respond
appropriately to their reasons. According to the present view, if one possesses
decisive reasons to adopt a certain attitude or course of action, then one is
rationally required to adopt that attitude or course of action (p. 11). Moreover, if one possesses decisive reason to
believe P, then one ipso facto possesses decisive reason not to believe ¬P. Hence, we may explain why it is irrational
for an agent to have inconsistent beliefs in terms of the requirement that they
respond appropriately to their reasons.
The upshot is that we are free to dispense with Belief Consistency and
Intention Consistency, and adopt Reasons Responsiveness in their place.
Pace
Lord, I maintain that there are cases in which an agent violates Intention
Consistency, but in which they do not violate Reasons Responsiveness. Hence,
Reasons Responsiveness is unable to explain all cases in which an agent is
irrational for having inconsistent intentions.
Consider
an agent, let’s call her Edna, who goes to the supermarket to purchase some
soup. She finds two identical cans of Campbell’s Tomato soup—can A and can B—on
the shelf and forms the intention to take can A rather than can B. Since both cans are indistinguishable in
every salient respect, each reason Edna possesses to (intend to) take can A—e.g.,
she loves soup, Campbell’s Tomato soup is her favourite, the soup is on sale,
etc.—is also a reason she possesses to intend to take can B. What Edna lacks is a reason to take can A
rather than can B or a reason to take can B rather than can A. Even so, Edna
may intend to take can A rather than can B.
Moreover, she does not appear to be guilty of irrationality for so doing.
If
the above analysis is right, then this poses a problem for Reasons
Responsiveness. This is because while it
is rationally permissible for Edna to intend to take can A rather than can B,
it is not rationally permissible for her to simultaneously intend to take can A
rather than can B and intend to take can B rather than can A. In sum, even in picking situations, one is
not rationally permitted to have inconsistent intentions. However, as we already noted, Edna has no
reason to (intend to) take can A rather than can B. We therefore cannot explain
why Edna is being irrational by saying she fails to respond appropriately to
her reasons. Ex hypothesi, she has
none. Hence, we appear to have a case in
which an agent has inconsistent intentions but does not fail to respond
correctly to the reasons she possesses.
Lord
anticipates a similar kind of objection in chapter 2 of his volume. However, the case Lord considers differs from
the above example in a crucial respect.
Lord considers a case in which an agent possesses sufficient (but not
decisive) reason to intend to F and sufficient (but not decisive) reason to not
intend to F. Such cases appear to pose a
problem for Reasons Responsiveness since possessing merely sufficient reason to
intend to F does not entail possessing decisive reason to not intend to ¬F. The apparent upshot is that Reasons
Responsiveness appears to allow that an agent with merely sufficient reasons
may have inconsistent intentions.
Lord
solves this problem by appealing to a principle he calls “Intentions Attenuate”
(p. 31). According to Intentions
Attenuate, if one adopts the intention to F, the adopted intention attenuates
the strength of all competing intentions, including the intention to ¬F. Intentions Attenuate contrasts with the
popular suggestion that forming an intention generates additional reasons to do
what one intends. Lord rejects this
proposal due to bootstrapping concerns (and rightly so). Intentions Attenuate avoids the boostrapping
problems because it does not entail that merely forming an intention generates
additional reasons. Rather, it entails
that an intention may either intensify or attenuate the weight of one’s
pre-existing reasons. However, it is the
very feature of Intentions Attenuate that allows it to avoid boostrapping
concerns that preclude it from solving the problem being limned in this post.
Since Edna has no reason to intend to take can A rather than can B, there are
no reasons to be either intensified or attenuated. The upshot is that Intentions Attenuate is of
no help to Lord in addressing the present worry.
One
possible diagnosis of why Intentions Attenuate is ineffective against the Edna example is that it appears to
presuppose that an intention is rationally permissible only if one has at least
some reason in its favour. (See p. 38 of
Lord’s discussion.) However, I believe intentions
stand in contrast to belief in precisely this regard. Plausibly, it is rationally permissible to
adopt a certain belief only if one has some reason in its favour, at least when
it comes to beliefs about external world.
For example, I cannot rationally believe that the number of stars in the
Milky Way is even given that I lack any reason to believe that it is. However, as the rational permissibility of
picking illustrates, it may be rationally permissible to adopt an intention
even if one has no reason in support of the intention. Given this fact, we cannot hope to make sense
of the consistency norms governing intentions in terms of an agent appropriately
responding to her possessed reasons.
Reference:
Lord,
E. (2018) The Importance of Being
Rational. Oxford University Press.