In his paper, “Reasons for Actions and Desires”, Ulrike Heuer
attempts to cast doubt on the Humean account of practical reasons (in the sense
of justificatory reasons for action). Heuer describes the Humean account as the
claim that “all practical reasons are based on a person’s given motives, or
desires” (p. 43). Moreover, he takes the
Humean to be committed to the following two claims:
(H1) Anything can be the object of a desire.
(H2) Actions can be justified (at least in some rudimentary sense) by showing that they are suited to lead to the satisfaction of a desire. (p. 52)
I will put aside the question of whether the Humean is necessarily
committed to (H1) and (H2) for the time being. Let us assume, for the sake of
argument, that she is. This, Heuer
argues, makes the Humean account susceptible to the following counterexample,
due to Warren Quinn:
Imagine that I had a disposition to turn on every radio within my reach, but not because I want to listen to music or news; as Quinn puts it: ‘Indeed, I do not turn them on in order to hear anything’. (p. 51)
The preceding case is supposed to present us with a scenario in
which an agent has a desire, but in which the desire fails to justify the actions
that would lead to the satisfaction of that desire. In order to constitute a genuine
counterexample to the Humean account, the Humean must be committed to saying
that the agent in Quinn’s example does in fact have a desire. In order to establish that the Humean is so
committed, Heuer notes that “most Humeans rely on” a functionalist conception
of desire, according to which an agent desires some end just in case she is
disposed to perform actions that would lead to achieving that end (p. 51). Since the agent in Quinn’s example satisfies
the right-hand-side of the preceding biconditional, it follows that
he has a desire.
One immediate problem with the preceding argument is that Heuer
fails to establish that the Humean must be committed to a functionalist (or
some relevantly similar) conception of desire.
He only claims that most
Humeans “rely” on a functionalist conception. However, it matters little if
most (or even all) Humeans rely on a functionalist conception of desire. What Heuer needs, if he is to establish that
the counterexample has force against the Humean, is that the Humean is necessarily committed to a
functionalist (or some relevantly similar) conception of desire, given her
other theoretical commitments. But, as we shall soon see, the Humean need not
be saddled with a functionalist conception of desire.
Perhaps it is Heuer’s recognition of the above point that leads him
to stress the Humean’s commitment to (H1).
The idea seems to be this: since the Humean is committed to the claim
that anything can be the object of a desire, it follows that she has no basis
for denying that the agent in Quinn’s example has a desire to turn on every
radio within reach. If this is supposed to be Heuer’s line of argument, then it
appears to rest on a mistake.
Specifically, Heuer appears to conflate two very distinct claims: the
claim that (i) there is no formal constraint on the content of a desire, and the claim that (ii) there is no formal constraint on the nature of a desire. While (H1) plausibly
entails (i), it does not entail (ii).
That is to say, a Humean need not be committed to saying that every
attitude that has the function of disposing an agent to act is a desire (i.e., the
functionalist conception of desire). For example, a Humean may consistently
subscribe to the following hybrid of a pleasure-based and action-based
conception of desire:
Pleasure-Action-Hybrid View (PAH)
S desires P iff S is disposed to take whatever actions S believes
necessary to bring about P, and S has this disposition in virtue of the fact
that S is disposed to take pleasure in the thought that P and displeasure in
the thought that not-P.
According to PAH, an agent counts as having a desire only in those
cases in which she is disposed to perform actions in a specific way; namely, in
virtue of being disposed to take pleasure in the thought of the desired outcome
obtaining, and displeasure in the thought of the desired outcome failing to
obtain. Significantly, this is not a formal constraint on the content of a
desire. It is formal constraint on what
constitutes a desire. Admittedly, it may
turn out that, as a matter of fact, a given agent may be disposed to take
pleasure or displeasure in the thought of only certain outcome’s obtaining and
not others. But his is an empirical and contingent matter. Not a formal
one. It remains true that, in principle,
anything may be the object of desire, even if it turns out that some things
seldom or never are. Hence, PAH is
perfectly consistent with (H1).
Moreover, PAH allows the Humean to adopt the following more nuanced
reply to Quinn’s example. According to
PAH, the agent in Quinn’s example has a desire to turn on every radio within
reach only if he is disposed to satisfy the desire in virtue of a disposition
to take pleasure in the thought of every radio within reach being on and
displeasure in the thought of every radio within reach being off. But once we substitute PAH for a
functionalist conception of desire, Quinn’s purported counterexample seems much
less compelling. If, on the one hand,
the agent in Quinn’s example is disposed to take pleasure in thought of the
radios being on, it seems less obvious that her desire to do so fails to
provide her with some (even if rudimentary) justification. After all, the fact that she is disposed to
take pleasure in the thought of the radios being on does seem to provide her
with some (even if rudimentary) justification for acting so as to satisfy her
desire. If, on the other hand, the agent
in Quinn’s example is not disposed to take pleasure in the thought of every
radio within reach being on (which seems truer to Quinn’s original intention),
then the Humean may consistently deny that the agent has a desire. She may, instead, hold that the agent merely
has a pathological urge or some other motivational state distinct from desire.
In short, the Humean need not be saddled with the view that all states that
dispose an agent to act so as to satisfy them are genuine desires.
Finally, there seems to be a fatal flaw in the overall structure of Heuer's appropriation of Quinn's example as an argument against the Humean account. Recall, Heuer defines the Humean account as the theory of rationality according to which “all practical reasons are based on a person’s given motives, or desires” (p. 43). The Humean is therefore committed to the claim that having a desire is a necessary condition for having a practical justification. However, the claim that all practical justification is based on desire does not entail that all desires provide practical justification. The former specifies a necessary condition for practical justification, while the latter specifies a sufficient condition. Hence, the Humean may grant that the desire of the agent described in Quinn’s example fails to provide him with a reason. However, it does not follow from the fact that some desires fail to provide practical justification that all desires fail to provide practical justification or that all practical justification is not based onn desire. In short, Heuer has not provided us with a valid argument against the claim that all practical justification is based on desires.
Finally, there seems to be a fatal flaw in the overall structure of Heuer's appropriation of Quinn's example as an argument against the Humean account. Recall, Heuer defines the Humean account as the theory of rationality according to which “all practical reasons are based on a person’s given motives, or desires” (p. 43). The Humean is therefore committed to the claim that having a desire is a necessary condition for having a practical justification. However, the claim that all practical justification is based on desire does not entail that all desires provide practical justification. The former specifies a necessary condition for practical justification, while the latter specifies a sufficient condition. Hence, the Humean may grant that the desire of the agent described in Quinn’s example fails to provide him with a reason. However, it does not follow from the fact that some desires fail to provide practical justification that all desires fail to provide practical justification or that all practical justification is not based onn desire. In short, Heuer has not provided us with a valid argument against the claim that all practical justification is based on desires.
No comments:
Post a Comment